logo资料库

【数学分析原理rudin】完整良心答案.pdf

第1页 / 共134页
第2页 / 共134页
第3页 / 共134页
第4页 / 共134页
第5页 / 共134页
第6页 / 共134页
第7页 / 共134页
第8页 / 共134页
资料共134页,剩余部分请下载后查看
Solutions to Principles of Mathematical Analysis (Walter Rudin) Jason Rosendale jason.rosendale@gmail.com December 19, 2011 This work was done as an undergraduate student: if you really don’t understand something in one of these proofs, it is very possible that it doesn’t make sense because it’s wrong. Any questions or corrections can be directed to jason.rosendale@gmail.com. Exercise 1.1a Let r be a nonzero rational number. We’re asked to show that x ∈ Q implies that (r + x) ∈ Q. Proof of the contrapositive: → r + x is rational → (∃p ∈ Q)(r + x = p) → (∃p, q ∈ Q)(q + x = p) → (∃p, q ∈ Q)(x = −q + p) assumed definition of rational we’re told that r is rational existence of additive inverses in Q Because p and q are members of the closed additive group of Q, we know that their sum is a member of Q. → (∃u ∈ Q)(x = u) → x is rational definition of rational By assuming that r +x is rational, we prove that x must be rational. By contrapositive, then, if x is irrational then r + x is irrational, which is what we were asked to prove. Exercise 1.1b Let r be a nonzero rational number. We’re asked to show that x ∈ Q implies that rx ∈ Q. Proof of the contrapositive: → rx is rational → (∃p ∈ Q)(rx = p) → (∃p ∈ Q)(x = r−1p) assumed definition of rational existence of multiplicative inverses in Q (Note that we can assume that r−1 exists only because we are told that r is nonzero.) Because r−1 and p are members of the closed multiplicative group of Q, we know that their product is also a member of Q. → (∃u ∈ Q)(x = u) → x is rational definition of rational By assuming that rx is rational, we prove that x must be rational. By contrapositive, then, if x is irrational then rx is irrational, which is what we were asked to prove. 1
Exercise 1.2 √ Proof by contradiction. If p/q where p and q are nonzero integers with no common divisors. 12 were rational, then we could write it as a reduced-form fraction in the form of √ 12 → p q = → ( p2 q2 = 12) → (p2 = 12q2) assumed It’s clear that 3|12q2, which means that 3|p2. By some theorem I can’t remember (possibly the definition of ‘prime’ itself), if a is a prime number and a|mn, then a|m ∨ a|n. Therefore, since 3|pp and 3 is prime, → 3|p → 9|p2 → (∃m ∈ N)(p2 = 9m) → (∃m ∈ N)(12q2 = 9m) → (∃m ∈ N)(4q2 = 3m) → (3|4q2) definition of divisibility substitution from p2 = 12q2 divide both sides by 3 definition of divisibility From the same property of prime divisors that we used previously, we know that 3|4 ∨ 3|q2: clearly doesn’t divide 4, so it must be the case that 3|q2. But if 3|qq, then 3|q ∨ 3|q. Therefore: it → (3|q) And this establishes a contradiction. We began by assuming that p and q had no common divisors, but we have shown that 3|p and 3|q. So our assumption must be wrong: there is no reduced-form rational number such that p √ 12. q = Exercise 1.3 a If x = 0 and xy = xz, then y = 1y = (x−1x)y = x−1(xy) = x−1(xz) = (x−1x)z = 1z = z Exercise 1.3 b If x = 0 and xy = x, then Exercise 1.3 c If x = 0 and xy = 1, then y = 1y = (x−1x)y = x−1(xy) = x−1x = 1 y = 1y = (x−1x)y = x−1(xy) = x−11 = x−1 = 1/x Exercise 1.3 d If x = 0, then the fact that x−1x =1 means that x is the inverse of x−1: that is, x = (x−1)−1 = 1/(1/x). Exercise 1.4 We are told that E is nonempty, so there exists some e ∈ E. By the definition of lower bound, (∀x ∈ E)(α ≤ x): so α ≤ e. By the definition of upper bound, (∀x ∈ E)(x ≤ β): so e ≤ β. Together, these two inequalities tell us that α ≤ e ≤ β. We’re told that S is ordered, so by the transitivity of order relations this implies α ≤ β. 2
Exercise 1.5 We’re told that A is bounded below. The field of real numbers has the greatest lower bound property, so we’re guaranteed to have a greatest lower bound for A. Let β be this greatest lower bound. To prove that −β is the least upper bound of −A, we must first show that it’s an upper bound. Let −x be an arbitrary element in −A: definition of membership in −A β = inf(A) → −x ∈ −A assumed → x ∈ A → β ≤ x → −β ≥ −x We began with an arbitrary choice of −x, so this proves that (∀ − x ∈ −A)(−β ≥ −x), which by definition tells us that −β is an upper bound for −A. To show that −β is the least such upper bound for −A, we choose some arbitrary element less than −β: consequence of 1.18(a) → α < −β → −α > β assumed consequence of 1.18(a) Remember that β is the greatest lower bound of A. If −α is larger than inf(A), there must be some element of A that is smaller than −α. (see above) → (∃x ∈ A)(x < −α) → (∃ − x ∈ −A)(−x > α) → !(∀ − x ∈ −A)(−x ≤ α) → α is not an upper bound of −A definition of upper bound This proves that any element less than −β is not an upper bound of −A. Together with the earlier proof consequence of 1.18(a) that −β is an upper bound of −A, this proves that −β is the least upper bound of −A. Exercise 1.6a The difficult part of this proof is deciding which, if any, of the familiar properties of exponents are considered axioms and which properties we need to prove. It seems impossible to make any progress on this proof unless we can assume that (bm)n = bmn. On the other hand, it seems clear that we can’t simply assume that (bm) 1 n = bm/n: this would make the proof trivial (and is essentially assuming what we’re trying to prove). As I understand this problem, we have defined xn in such a way that it is trivial to prove that (xa)b = xab when a and b are integers. And we’ve declared in theorem 1.21 that, by definition, the symbol x 1 n is the element such that (xn) 1 n = x. But we haven’t defined exactly what it might mean to combine an integer power like n and some arbitrary inverse like 1/r. We are asked to prove that these two elements do, in fact, combine in the way we would expect them to: (xn)1/r = xn/r. Unless otherwise noted, every step of the following proof is justified by theorem 1.21. 3
→ bm = bm → ((bm) 1 → ((bm) 1 n )n = bm n )nq = bmq assumed definition of x 1 n We were told that m mq = np. Therefore: n = p q which, by the definition of the equality of rational numbers, means that → ((bm) 1 → ((bm) 1 n )nq = bnp n )qn = bpn commutativity of multiplication From theorem 12.1, we can take the n root of each side to get: → ((bm) 1 n )q = bp From theorem 12.1, we can take the q root of each side to get: → (bm) 1 n = (bp) 1 q Exercise 1.6b As in the last proof, we assume that br+s = brbs when r and s are integers and try to prove that the operation q where m, n, p, q ∈ Z and works in a similar way when r and s are rational numbers. Let r = m n, q = 0. n and let s = p m q 1 nq 1 nq nq mq+pn n + p → br+s = b → br+s = b → br+s = (bmq+pn) → br+s = (bmqbpn) → br+s = (bmq) → br+s = (b pn mq nq ) nq )(b → br+s = (b m p n )(b q ) → br+s = (br)(bs) definition of addition for rationals from part a legal because mq and pn are integers 1 nq corollary of 1.21 from part a 1 nq (bpn) Exercise 1.6c We’re given that b > 1. Let r be a rational number. Proof by contradiction that br is an upper bound of B(r): → br is not an upper bound of B(r) → (∃x ∈ B(r))(x > br) hypothesis of contradiction formalization of the hypothesis By the definition of membership in B(r), x = bt where t is rational and t ≤ r. → (∃t ∈ Q)(bt > br ∧ t ≤ r) It can be shown that b−t > 0 (see theorem S1, below) so we can multiply this term against both sides of the inequality. → (∃t ∈ Q)(btb−t > brb−t ∧ t ≤ r) → (∃t ∈ Q)(bt−t > br−t ∧ t ≤ r) → (∃t ∈ Q)(1 > br−t ∧ r − t ≥ 0) → (∃t ∈ Q)(1−(r−t) > b ∧ r − t ≥ 0) → 1 > b theorem S2 from part b And this establishes our contradiction, since we were given that b > 1. Our initial assumption must have been incorrect: br is, in fact, an upper bound of B(r). We must still prove that it is the least upper bound of B(r), though. To do so, let α represent an arbitrary rational number such that bα < br. From this, we need to 4
prove that α < r. → bα < br → bαb−r < brb−r → bα−r < br−r → bα−r < 1 hypothesis of contradiction theorem S2 from part b from part b Exercise 1.7 a Proof by induction. Let S = {n : bn − 1 ≥ n(b − 1)}. We can easily verify that 1 ∈ S. Now, assume that k ∈ S: hypothesis of induction definition of membership in S we’re told that b > 1. → k ∈ S → bk − 1 ≥ k(b − 1) → bbk − 1 ≥ k(b − 1) → bk+1 − b ≥ k(b − 1) → bk+1 ≥ k(b − 1) + b → bk+1 − 1 ≥ k(b − 1) + b − 1 → bk+1 − 1 ≥ (k + 1)(b − 1) → k + 1 ∈ S By induction, this proves that (∀n ∈ N)(bn − 1 ≥ n(b − 1)). definition of membership in S Alternatively, we could prove this using the same identity that Rudin used in the proof of 1.21. From the distributive property we can verify that bn − an = (b − a)(bn−1a0 + bn−2a1 + . . . + b0an−1). So when a = 1, this becomes bn − 1 = (b − 1)(bn−1 + bn−2 + . . . + b0). And since b > 1, each term in the bn−k series is greater than 1, so bn − 1 ≥ (b − 1)(1n−1 + 1n−2 + . . . + 10) = (b − 1)n. Exercise 1.7 b → n(b 1 → n(b 1 n − 1) = n(b 1 n − 1) = (1 + 1 + . . . + 1) n − 1) n times n − 1) (b 1 → n(b 1 n − 1) = (1n−1 + 1n−2 + . . . + 10)(b 1 n − 1) It can be shown that bk > 1 when b > 1, k > 0 (see theorem S4). Replacing 1 with b 1 inequality: n gives us the → n(b 1 n − 1) ≤ ((b 1 n )n−1 + (b 1 n )n−2 + . . . + (b 1 n )0)(b 1 n − 1) Now we can use the algebraic identity bn − an = (bn−1a0 + bn−2a1 + . . . + b0an−1)(b − a): → n(b 1 → n(b 1 n − 1) ≤ ((b 1 n − 1) ≤ (b − 1) n )n − 1) Exercise 1.7 c → n > (b − 1)/(t − 1) → n(t − 1) > (b − 1) → n(t − 1) > (b − 1) ≥ n(b 1 → n(t − 1) > n(b 1 → (t − 1) > (b 1 → t > b 1 n − 1) n − 1) n n − 1) assumed this holds because n, t, and b are greater than 1 from part b transitivity of order relations n > 0 → n−1 > 0 would be a trivial proof 5
Exercise 1.7 d We’re told that bw < y, which means that 1 < yb−w. Using the substitution yb−w = t with part (c), we’re lead directly to the conclusion that we can select n such that yb−w > b 1 n , which is what we were asked to prove. As a corollary, the fact that b 1 n . From this we get y > bw+ 1 n > 1 means that bw+ 1 n > bw. Exercise 1.7 e We’re told that bw > y, which means that bwy−1 > 1. Using the substitution bwy−1 = t with part (c), we’re lead directly to the conclusion that we can select n such that bwy−1 > b 1 n . Multiplying both sides by y gives us bw > b 1 n > y, which is what we were asked to prove. As a corollary, the fact that b 1 n > 1 > 0 means that, upon taking the reciprocals, we have b −1 n < 1 and therefore bw− 1 −1 n gives us bw− 1 n y. Multiplying this by b n < bw. Exercise 1.7 f We’ll prove that bx = y by showing that the assumptions bx > y and bx < y lead to contradictions. If bx > y, then from part (e) we can choose n such that bx > bx− 1 n > y. From this we see that x − 1 upper bound of A that is smaller than x. This is a contradiction, since we’ve assumed that x =sup(A). n is an If bx < y, then from part (d) we can choose n such that y > bx+ 1 n > bx. From this we see that x is not an upper bound of A. This is a contradiction, since we’ve assumed that x is the least upper bound of A. Having ruled out these two possibilities, the trichotomy property of ordered fields forces us to conclude that bx = y. Exercise 1.7 g Assume that there are two elements such that bw = y and bx = y. Then by the transitivity of equality relations, bw = by, although this seems suspiciously simple. Exercise 1.8 In any ordered set, all elements of the set must be comparable (the trichotomy rule, definition 1.5). We will show by contradiction that (0, 1) is not comparable to (0, 0) in any potential ordered field containing C. First, we assume that (0, 1) > (0, 0) : → (0, 1) > (0, 0) → (0, 1)(0, 1) > (0, 0) hypothesis of contradiction definition 1.17(ii) of ordered fields We assumed here that (0, 0) can take the role of 0 in definition 1.17 of an ordered field. This is a safe assumption because the uniqueness property of the additive identity shows us immediately that (0, 0) + (a, b) = (a, b) → (0, 0) = 0. → (−1, 0) > (0, 0) → (−1, 0)(0, 1) > (0, 0) → (0,−1) > (0, 0) definition of complex multiplication definition 1.17(ii) of ordered fields, since we initially assumed (0, 1) > 0 definition of complex multiplication It might seem that we have established our contradiction as soon as we concluded that (−1, 0) > 0 or (0,−1) > 0. However, we’re trying to show that the complex field cannot be an ordered field under any ordered relation, even a bizarre one in which −1 > −i > 0. However, we’ve shown that (0, 1) and (0,−1) are both greater than zero. Therefore: → (0,−1) + (0, 1) > (0, 0) + (0, 1) → (0, 0) > (0, 1) definition 1.17(i) of ordered fields definition of complex multiplication This conclusion is in contradiction of trichotomy, since we initially assumed that (0, 0) < (0, 1). Next, we assume that (0, 1) < (0, 0): 6
→ (0, 0) > (0, 1) → (0, 0) + (0,−1) > (0, 1) + (0,−1) → (0,−1) > (0, 0) → (0,−1)(0,−1) > (0, 0) → (−1, 0) > (0, 0) → (−1, 0)(0,−1) > (0, 0) → (0, 1) > (0, 0) hypothesis of contradiction definition 1.17(i) of ordered fields definition of complex addition definition 1.17(ii) of ordered fields definition of complex multiplication definitino 1.17(ii) of ordered fields, since we’ve established (0,−1) > (0, 0) definition of complex multiplication Once again trichotomy has been violated. Proof by contradiction that (0, 1) = (0, 0): if we assume that (0, 1) = (0, 0) we’re led to the conclusion that (a, b) = (0, 0) for every complex number, since (a, b) = a(0, 1)4 + b(0, 1) = a(0, 0) + b(0, 0) = (0, 0). By the transitivity of equivalence relations, this would mean that every element is equal to every other. And this is in contradiction of definition 1.12 of a field, where we’re told that there are at least two distinct elements: the additive identity (’0’) and the multiplicative identity (’1’). Exercise 1.9a To prove that this relation turns C into an ordered set, we need to show that it satisfies the two requirements in definition 1.5. Proof of transitivity: → (a, b) < (c, d) ∧ (c, d) < (e, f ) → [a < c ∨ (a = c ∧ b < d)] ∧ [c < e ∨ (c = e ∧ d < f )] → (a < c ∧ c < e) ∨ (a < c ∧ c = e ∧ d < f ) definition of this order relation assumption ∨(a = c ∧ b < d ∧ c < e) ∨ (a = c ∧ b < d ∧ c = e ∧ d < f ) → (a < e) ∨ (a < e ∧ d < f ) ∨ (a < e ∧ b < d) ∨ (a = e ∧ b < f ) distributivity of logical operators transitivity of order relation on R Although we’re falling back on the the transitivity of an order relation, we are not assuming what we’re trying to prove. We’re trying to prove the transitivity of the dictionary order relation on C, and this relation is defined in terms of the standard order relation on R. This last step is using the transitivity of this standard order relation on R and is not assuming that transitivity holds for the dictionary order relation. → (a < e) ∨ (a < e) ∨ (a < e) ∨ (a = e ∧ b < f ) → a < e ∨ (a = e ∧ b < f ) → (a, b) < (e, f ) To prove that the trichotomy property holds for the dictionary relation on Q, we rely on the trichotomy property of the underlying standard order relation on R. Let (a, b) and (c, d) be two elements in C. From the standard order relation, we know that p ∧ q → p p ∨ p → p definition of this order relation → (a, b) ∈ C ∧ (c, d) ∈ C → a, b, c, d ∈ R → (a < c) ∨ (a > c) ∨ (a = c) → (a < c) ∨ (a > c) ∨ (a = c ∧ (b < d ∨ b > d ∨ b = d)) → (a < c) ∨ (a > c) ∨ (a = c ∧ b < d) ∨ (a = c ∧ b > d) ∨(a = c ∧ b = d) ∨(a, b) = (c, d) → (a, b) < (c, d) ∨ (a, b) > (c, d) ∨ (a, b) < (c, d) ∨ (a, b) > (c, d) → (a, b) < (c, d) ∨ (a, b) > (c, d) ∨ (a, b) = (c, d) assumed definition of a complex number trichotomy of the order relation on R trichotomy of the order relation on R distributivity of the logical operators definition of the dictionary order relation And this is the definition of the trichotomy law, so we have proven that the dictionary order turns the 7
complex numbers into an ordered set. Exercise 1.9b C does not have the least upper bound property under the dictionary order. Let E = {(0, a) : a ∈ R}. This subset is just the imaginary axis in the complex plane. This subset clearly has an upper bound, since (x, 0) > (0, a) for any x > 0. But it does not have a least upper bound: for any proposed upper bound (x, y) with x > 0, we see that (x, y) < ( , y) < (0, a) x 2 So that ( x 2 , y) is an upper bound less than our proposed least upper bound, which is a contradiction. Exercise 1.10 This is just straightforward algebra, and is too tedious to write out. Exercise 1.11 If we choose w = z|z| and choose r = |z|, then we can easily verify that |w| = 1 and that rw = |z| z|z| = z. Exercise 1.12 √ √ Set ai zi and bi = ¯zi and use the Cauchy-Schwarz inequality (theorem 1.35). This gives us n j=1 ¯zj √ zj ≤ n n | ¯zj|2 |√ zj|2 j=1 j=1 2 which is equivalent to |z1 + z2 + . . . + zn|2 ≤ (|z1| + |z2| + . . . + |zn|)2 Taking the square root of each side shows that |z1 + z2 + . . . + zn| ≤ |z1| + |z2| + . . . + |zn| which is what we were asked to prove. Exercise 1.13 |x − y|2 = (x − y)(x − y) = (x − y)(¯x − ¯y) = x¯x − x¯y − y¯x + y ¯y = x¯x − (x¯y + y¯x) + y ¯y = |x|2 − 2Re(x¯y) + |y|2 ≥ |x|2 − 2|Re(x¯y)| + |y|2 ≥ |x|2 − 2|x¯y| + |y|2 = |x|2 − 2|x||¯y| + |y|2 = |x|2 − 2|x||y| + |y|2 = (|x| − |y|)(|x| − |y|) = (|x| − |y|)(|¯x| − |¯y|) = (|x| − |y|)(|x| − |y|) = ||x| − |y||2 Theorem 1.31(a) Theorem 1.31(c), definition 1.32 x ≤ |x|, so −|x| ≥ |x|. Theorem 1.33(d) Theorem 1.33(c) Theorem 1.33(b) Theorem 1.33(b) Theorem 1.31(a) This chain of inequalities shows us that ||x| − |y||2 ≤ |x − y|2. Taking the square root of both sides results in the claim we wanted to prove. 8
分享到:
收藏